Saturday, May 29, 2010
an every day emergency
Wednesday, May 26, 2010
boos for boonin
The problem with Boonin's argument wasn't that it was strange and Lee's wasn't... although, come to think of it, it was really strange. I've always been intrigued by what, to me, is a glaring weakness in the kinds of “sophisticated” pro-abortion arguments that philosophers like David Boonin and Judith Jarvis Thomson defend (hers is the famous 'unconscious violinist' argument); namely, that their substance is nothing more than a totally bizarre scenario. Whereas pregnancy is absolutely normal (so normal, in fact, that it is the means by which every one of us got here), Boonin and Thomson draw out hypotheticals that are nearly inconceivable. If you watch the Pomona video, you will see that throughout the debate, Boonin kept feeling forced to manipulate variables of his bone marrow story in hopes to make it look more similar to the case of unwanted pregnancy. And Lee didn't even have to point out the dissimilarities; Boonin already knew they were there (largely due to pro-choice philosophers who, Boonin said, had pointed them out to him before). But as much as I give Boonin credit for his valiant efforts to "fix" his oddball story, it was still just that: an oddball story. And he still sounded silly- not intellectual- when telling it.
For example: at one point during the question-and-answer session, Boonin started describing a scenario where “you do a fun activity and the fun activity leads it to being the case that you can then keep me alive." He explained, “if you engage in this fun activity, some weird change in your bone marrow will take place and then you’ll become an appropriate match." What? This was his attempt to make his hypothetical more parallel with the fact that sex is an enjoyable activity, but come on... I don't mean to pick on Boonin, but he is one of the leading philosophers in defense of abortion today, and this is his central argument?
I have not even discussed the actual flaws in his reasoning; for an argument does not necessarily fail just because it is weird. But indeed, Boonin's argument does unravel philosophically since there are several morally relevant differences between his bone marrow hypothetical and a woman's unwanted pregnancy. These differences include, but are not limited to, the material act (abortion as a direct killing and refusing bone marrow as an allowing someone to die), special responsibilities (parents possess certain natural responsibilities for their children that random bone marrow partners do not possess for strangers), and fairness of trade (the burdens of pregnancy, while difficult, are in no way proportional to death).
Needless to say, by the end of the debate (if not before), the audience seemed to have turned on Boonin. Lee did not have to point out the flaws in Boonin's argument; he had pointed out most of them himself. And when the question-and-answer session finally rolled around, every cross-examining student save one wanted Boonin to explain himself. Although he appeared to be the one putting forth a sophisticated argument that night, Boonin had somehow remained on the defensive virtually the entire time. Students afterward wanted to know why certain parts of his scenario didn't match up, or how the implications of his argument wouldn't just as easily justify slavery... I almost felt badly for him.
I can't tell if Boonin just feels obligated to "stick to his guns" since he has written so extensively in defense of abortion and is now well-known in that field, or if he truly believes his position is correct. I would naturally assume the latter, but from some of his own comments in this debate, it seems he is aware of the many weaknesses of his argument. At any rate, if bizarre-o scenarios about unplugging transplant tubes, unique sperm donor agreements, removable pace-makers, and "weird change[s] in your bone marrow" (all of which Boonin referenced in this video) are what a sophisticated pro-choicer is trying to foist, it looks like even the most unsophisticated pro-lifer has nothing to worry about.
Vita Pro Omni!
Saturday, May 22, 2010
pro-life love
"Love is indeed “ecstasy”, not in the sense of a moment of intoxication, but rather as a journey, an ongoing exodus out of the closed inward-looking self towards its liberation through self-giving, and thus towards authentic self-discovery and indeed the discovery of God: “Whoever seeks to gain his life will lose it, but whoever loses his life will preserve it” (Lk 17:33), as Jesus says throughout the Gospels (cf. Mt 10:39; 16:25; Mk 8:35; Lk 9:24; Jn 12:25). In these words, Jesus portrays his own path, which leads through the Cross to the Resurrection: the path of the grain of wheat that falls to the ground and dies, and in this way bears much fruit. Starting from the depths of his own sacrifice and of the love that reaches fulfilment therein, he also portrays in these words the essence of love and indeed of human life itself."
Wednesday, May 19, 2010
dualism: a do or a don't?
Saturday, May 15, 2010
blood money
Wednesday, May 12, 2010
moral relativism: "feet firmly planted in mid-air"* (part 2)
Argument from ToleranceMany people see relativism as necessary for promoting tolerance, non-judgmentalism, and inclusiveness, for they think if you believe your moral position is correct and others' incorrect you are closed-minded and intolerant. They usually base this premise on the well-known differences of opinion on morality between cultures and individuals. So, the moral relativist embraces the view that one should not judge other cultures and individuals, for to do so would be intolerant. There are at least four problems with this argument, all of which maintain that tolerance (rightly understood) and relativism are actually incompatible with each other.Tolerance supports objective morality, not relativismIronically, the call to tolerance by relativists presupposes the existence of at least one nonrelative, universal, and objective norm: tolerance... [I]f everyone ought to be tolerant, then tolerance is an objective moral norm. And therefore, moral relativism is false. Also, tolerance presupposes that there is something good about being tolerant, such as being able to learn from others with whom one disagrees or impart knowledge and wisdom to that person. But that presupposes objective moral values, namely, that knowledge and wisdom are good things. Moreover, tolerance presupposes that someone may be correct about his or her moral perspective. That is to say, it seems that part of the motivation for advocating tolerance is to encourage people to be open to the possibility that one may be able to gain truth and insight (including moral truth and insight) from another who may possess it. If that is the case, then there are objective moral truths one can learn.In addition, tolerance presupposes a moral judgment of another's viewpoint. That is to say, I can only be tolerant of those ideas that I think are mistaken. I am not tolerant of that with which I agree; I embrace it. And I am not tolerant of that for which I have no interest (e.g., European professional soccer); I merely have benign neglect for it. (That is, I don't care one way or another.)Relativism is itself a closed-minded and intolerant positionAfter all, the relativist dogmatically asserts that there is no moral truth. To illustrate this, consider a dialogue (based loosely on a real-life exchange) between a high school teacher and her student Elizabeth. The teacher instructs her class, "Welcome, students. This is the first day of class, and so I want to lay down some ground rules. First, because no one has the truth about morality, you should be open-minded to the opinions of your fellow students." The teacher recognizes the raised hand of Elizabeth who asks, "If nobody has the truth, isn't that a good reason for me not to listen to my fellow students? After all, if nobody has the truth, why should I waste my time listening to other people and their opinions? What's the point? Only if somebody has the truth does it make sense to be open-minded. Don't you agree?""No, I don't. Are you claiming to know the truth? Isn't that a bit arrogant and dogmatic?""Not at all. Rather I think it's dogmatic, as well as arrogant, to assert that no single person on earth knows the truth. After all, have you met every single person in the world and quizzed them exhaustively? If not, how can you make such a claim? Also, I believe it is actually quite the opposite of arrogance to say that I will alter my opinions to fit the truth whenever and wherever I find it. And if I happen to think I have good reason to believe I do know the truth and would like to share it with you, why wouldn't you listen to me? Why would you automatically discredit my opinion before it is even uttered? I thought we were supposed to listen to everyone's opinion."Relativism is judgmental, exclusivist, and partisanThis may seem like an odd thing to say as the relativist would like you to think his viewpoint is nonjudgmental, inclusivist, and neutral when it comes to moral beliefs. But consider the following.First, the relativist says if you believe in objective moral truth, you are wrong. Hence, relativism is judgmental. Second, it follows from this that relativism is excluding your beliefs from the realm of legitimate options. Thus, relativism is exclusivist. And third, because relativism is exclusivist, all nonrelativists are automatically not members of the "correct thinking" party. So, relativism is partisan.Tolerance only makes sense within the framework of a moral order, for it is within such a framework that one can morally justify tolerating some things while not tolerating others. For tolerance without a moral framework, or absolute tolerance, leads to a dogmatic relativism, and thus to an intolerance of any viewpoint that does not embrace relativism. It is no wonder that in such a climate of "tolerance" any person who maintains that there is an objective moral order to which society ought to subscribe is greeted with contempt.The "tolerance" of moral relativism either condones barbarism or is self-refuting.As I pointed out above, some moral relativists embrace tolerance because they believe that such a posture is appropriate given the diversity of moral and cultural traditions in the world today. Humanist author Xiaorong Li points out the fallacy in this reasoning:
But the existence of moral diversity does no more to justify that we ought to respect different moral values than the existence of disease, hunger, torture, and slavery do to justify that we ought to value them. Empirical claims thus are not suitable as the basis for developing moral principles such as "Never judge other cultures" or "We ought to tolerate different values." ...What if the respected or tolerated culture disrespects and advocates violence against individuals who dissent? When a girl fights to escape female genital circumcision or foot-binding or arranged marriage, or when a widow does not want to be burned to death to honor her dead husband, the relativist is obligated to "respect" the cultural or traditional customs from which the individuals are trying to escape. In doing so, the relativist is not merely disrespecting the individual but effectively endorsing the moral ground for rape, torture, and murder. On moral issues, ethical relativists cannot possibly remain neutral- they are committed either to the individual or to the dominant force within the culture.Relativists have made explicit one central value- equal respect and tolerance of other ways of life, which they insist to be absolute and universal. Ethical relativism is thus repudiated by itself.
Sunday, May 9, 2010
our first home
Marjorie Dannenfelser, President of the Susan B. Anthony List, passed on a beautiful story to me last night. She wrote:
While serving the poor in Calcutta, Mother Teresa once found a young boy on the streets and brought him back to Shishu Bhavan- one of the homes she established for impoverished and disabled children. There, the boy was given food and clean clothes- but he ran away! The next day, again the boy was brought back to Shishu Bhavan, and again he ran away. Three times, the boy ran away, until on the third day, one of the Sisters followed him.
"Why do you keep running away from home?" the Sister asked when she caught up to him. The boy pointed to a tree, under which a woman was standing, cooking a simple meal of food she had found in the garbage. "But this is home," he said. "This is where my mother is."
So simple. So beautiful. "Our mothers are our first home."
A mother's love for her child is powerful... strong... miracle-working. I have experienced this love firsthand through my own mother, and remember, in particular, how important her love was to me as a little girl. On my first day of kindergarten, I didn't want to leave my mom. She knew that I might get homesick, so she gave me a little picture of she and I together (left) to put into the clear front pocket of my Barney backpack. I would look at that picture throughout the day because it made me feel better; I was looking at my home... my mommy.
Love is the reason we stand for life. Abortion is the complete opposite of love, as, in Marjorie's words, it breaks down the door to our first home. And because it is impossible to separate the well-being of a mother from that of her child, we know that for every one of the 115,000 children suffering from abortion every day, there is a mother somewhere, suffering, too. When we destroy motherhood, we destroy love.
Today, on Mother's Day, thank your mom for choosing life. Thank her for her strong love that protected you when you were among the most small and helpless in society. And may each of us be strengthened in our resolve to protect all unborn children who are small and helpless just like we were.
I love you, Mommy.
Vita Pro Omni!